Chapter 45: Body & Soul
Terrance
lycidas2 at earthlink.net
Fri Apr 12 07:06:24 CDT 2002
Scott Badger wrote:
>
> Page 25. I'm not even through the intro yet and the Pynchon parallels are
> quite, er, prolific...Haven't gotten far enough to offer any expansion
> (maybe you can rouse Charles) but you might be interested in this:
>
> "No great Greek ever wrote any recollections that would serve to fix a phase
> of experience for his inner eye. Not even Socrates has told, regarding his
> inward life, anything important in our sense of the word. It is questionable
> indeed whether for a Classical mind it was even possible to react to motive
> forces that are presupposed in the production of a Parzival, a Hamlet, or a
> Werther. In Plato we fail to observe any conscious evolution of doctrine;
> his separate works are merely treatises written from very different
> standpoints which he took up from time to time, and it gave him no concern
> whether and how they hung together." page 10
P seems to like Macrohistory or Universal theories of history, at least
he likes to use them in his fictions. Adams or course, St. Augustine,
Freud, Joachim de Fiore, Etc......that being said, I don't know of any
hard evidence that he read Spengler.
Spengler is a classic good read. I must say, however, this idea about
the Classical mind is utter nonsense. Sorry, but these universal
theories of the world and humanity are always full of lots of wonderful
but silly things. The example of Plato is almost too silly to comment
on. There is no conscious evolution of doctrine in Plato's dialogues.
Why not? And, each one takes up a different standpoint. Why? What is
Plato up to?
First, the doctrine:
On Platonic Virtue:
>From The Works of Plato, Jowett Tans, Irwin Edman:
The world of Platonic ideas, if it is one thing more
than another, is a world of values. Shining in implacable
eternal beauty, it constitutes a metaphysician's dream of
order amid the harassing and perplexing confusions of the
world of experience. For though Socrates in the Parmenides
is made to admit that in strict logic there must be Ideas,
also, of mud and hair and dust and dirt, as well as of
Beauty, Goodness, and Truth, he makes the admission reluctantly.
"What," as Professor Dewey suggests, "is the realm of
ideas in Plato, but the realm of things with all their im-
perfections removed." It is a universe constituted out of
the purified essences of the heart's desire. It is a realm
of changelessness for a heart saddened by the spectacle of inevitable
change. It is order for a mind perturbed by a
night-mare of endless chaos. It is the cosmos of reason of which
one may have a glimpse in any thing of beauty, in any
item of clarity. in the turbulent regions here below the
moon. It is the pattern which the mind of man may come to know,
and the life of man and of society within limits exemplify
and follow.For in addition to being a metaphysician and a poet,
Plato was also, perhaps above all, a moralist. He was not
a moralizer. He was a moralist in the grand architectonic
sense of believing that it was possible to educate men, at
least a small group of philosophic spirits, to a disciplined
knowledge of reality, as contrasted with veering opinions
about appearance; in the light and by the guidance of
that steady vision of the truth, they could bring to being
on earth something like a realization, at least a decent ap-
proximation of the divine pattern of the good. Plato's
whole enterprise, taken in the total context of the dialogues,
might be said to be that of indicating how the Good Life might
be lived. The whole body of the Platonic writings aims
to define the Good Life, to define it, not in a formula, but
in a series of suggestions, converging around the ideas of
unity, consistency and validity in the individual soul, and
in that co-operation of souls which is Society or the State.
The Early Socratic dialogues indicate the insistence of
Plato, here closely fo11owing his master, on the identity of
virtue and knowledge.
On the Dialogues hanging together:
"Dialectic" is Plato's word, it comes from "dialegesthai,"
to talk with, and Plato's philosophy is worked out in
Dialogues. The dialectician must deal with the answers he
gets to questions he asks, and both questioner and
questioned are the method of the dialogues. Since there are
unlimited interlocutors, there can be no system of the
dialogues. All things may be part of a single system, but it
is beyond our knowledge according to Plato. Each of us encounters the
real in
our own way, and these encounters do not constitute a single
method or system. So the dialogues are fragments,
philosophical fragments that establish order in a limited
domain. The order of each dialogue is dialectical in
endeavoring to preserve and transcend the standpoint of the
other. Dialectic succeeds, not when one maintains a tension or an
agon or a fixed position against the other, but when one
loses and transcends his position in interaction with the
other.
"We have, then, with Adams and Nietzsche, a
common prognosis of a nihilistic future, and two diverging reactions
that may be
roughly characterized as Apollonian rejection and Dionysian embrace.
Both
reactions are incorporated into Pynchon's work, where they correspond
roughly to a
humanity-centered norm without effective defenders and to the
dehumanizing forces
and/or conspiracies that besiege it. Yet another antithesis that
correlates with
these reactions is that between the scenario of an existential
wasteland that
is prey only to a growing spiritual emptiness and entropy's
indifferent
ravagings, and the scenario of a world in the grip of fanatical cabals
that
seek control of the historical process. It would not be an unfair
summation of
Pynchon's development to say that he moves from the scenario in his
early short
stories to the most urgent consideration of the second in Gravity's
Rainbow. In
between, the two possibilities form, in various mixtures and guises,
the
onto-epistemological cruxes that have fascinated critics"
These considerations constitute the parameters that generate
the complex RELIGIOUS DIALECTIC (my caps) of Pynchon's
fiction: a fluctuating tension between nostalgia for cosmic
harmony and commitment to amoral power worship, superimposed
upon the fluctuating tension between the notion of a
neutral, structureless universe and that of a universe
infiltrated by insidious structures of Control.
*The Gnostic Pynchon* Dwight Eddins, Cutter's University
Press 1990
More information about the Pynchon-l
mailing list