The alien hypothesis?
Paul Mackin
paul.mackin at verizon.net
Wed Oct 19 12:26:43 CDT 2005
On Oct 19, 2005, at 5:10 AM, Otto wrote:
> This reminds me of Jonathan Culler's "On Deconstruction. Theory and
> Criticism after Structuralism" (Cornell Univ., Ithaca, New York,
> 1982). Maybe you should check the second chapter "Deconstruction"
> for Nietzsche's reversal of cause and effect where it is shown how
> the cause is imagined after the effect has been suffered. Got it
> only in German.
>
> Otto
I don't have a copy of the Culler book but here from the New York
Review is John Searle's reaction to Niezsche's cause/effect reversal
as Culler presents it.
Although NYReview published a long rebuttal of Searle's review (also
an equally long counter-rebuttal) I don't think any challange was
made to Searle on the Neizsche matter.
Since the review contains relevant direct quotes from Culler, it
should serve present purposes.
Anyway, here's what Searle wrote:
2.
Deconstruction, as Culler describes it, may not sound very promising,
but the test of a method of textual analysis lies in its results, so
let us now turn to some of the examples where Culler and Derrida show
us how deconstruction is supposed to work. Culler's paradigm example,
the one he presents to show how the various characterizations and
operations of deconstruction "might converge in practice" (p. 86), is
what he describes as Nietzsche's deconstruction of causality.
Suppose one feels a pain. This causes one to look for a cause
and spying, perhaps, a pin, one posits a link and reverses the
perceptual or phenomenal order, pain…pin, to produce a causal
sequence, pin…pain. "The fragment of the outside world of which we
become conscious comes after the effect that has been produced on us
and is projected a posteriori as its 'cause"' [p. 86].
So far this does not sound very deconstructive of anything. Culler
thinks otherwise, and to get an idea of the deconstructionist style
of argument it is worth quoting his commentary at some length:
Let us be as explicit as possible about what this simple example
implies…. The experience of pain, it is claimed, causes us to
discover the pin [his italics] and thus causes the production of a
cause [my italics]. To deconstruct causality one must operate with
the notion of cause and apply it to causation itself [p. 87].
Thus one is "asserting the indispensability of causation while
denying it any rigorous justification" (p. 88). Furthermore,
the deconstruction reverses the hierarchical opposition of the
causal scheme. The distinction between cause and effect makes the
cause an origin, logically and temporally prior. The effect is
derived, secondary, dependent upon the cause. Without exploring the
reasons for or the implications of this hierarchization, let us note
that, working within the opposition, the deconstruction upsets the
hierarchy by producing an exchange of properties. If the effect is
what causes the cause to become a cause, then the effect, not the
cause, should be treated as the origin. By showing that the argument
which elevates cause can be used to favor effect, one uncovers and
undoes the rhetorical operation responsible for the hierarchization
and one produces a significant displacement [p. 88; my italics].
I believe that far from demonstrating the power of deconstruction,
Culler's discussion of this example is a tissue of confusions. Here
are several of the most glaring mistakes.
1. There is nothing whatever in the example to support the view that
the effect "causes the production of a cause" or that the effect
"causes the cause to become a cause." The experience of pain causes
us to look for its cause and thus indirectly causes the discovery of
the cause. The idea that it produces the cause is exactly counter to
what the example actually shows.
2. The word "origin" is being used in two quite distinct senses. If
"origin" means causal origin then the pin is the causal origin of the
pain. If "origin" means epistemic origin, how we go about finding
out, then the experience of pain is the origin of our discovery of
its cause. But it is a simple confusion to conclude from this that
there is some unitary sense of "origin" in which "the effect and not
the cause should be treated as the origin."
3. There isn't any logical hierarchy between cause and effect in the
first place since the two are correlative terms: one is defined in
terms of the other. The OED, for example, defines "cause" as "that
which produces an effect" and it defines "effect" as "something
caused or produced."
4. Contrary to what Culler claims, nothing in the example shows that
causation lacks any "rigorous justification," or that any
"significant displacement" has come about. Our common sense
prejudices about causation deserve careful scrutiny and criticism,
but nothing in Culler's discussion forces any change in our most
naive views about causation.
>
> John Doe wrote:
>
>
>> LOL! "semantic constructs" my ass...
>> matter of fact,next time a person falls on his ass, tell him,
>> "hey! dude; you just suffered from the effects of a semantic
>> construct!" Talk about sucking up to dogma; the people who wrote
>> all those texts - oh pardon me, I should say 'generated' those
>> texts, since we all know the individual "I" is an illusion;
>> another "sematic construct"
>>
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
> ___________________________________________________________
> Gesendet von Yahoo! Mail - Jetzt mit 1GB Speicher kostenlos - Hier
> anmelden: http://mail.yahoo.de
>
More information about the Pynchon-l
mailing list